Cartesian Self

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In philosophy, the Cartesian Self, a concept developed by René Descartes within Mind-body dualism , is the term provided for an individual's mind or for a human being both of these being given contrasting meanings by Descartes. In the simple view the self can be viewed as just the mind which is separate from the body as well as the outside world. The simple self, The mind, also stands to be capable of thinking about itself and its existence.[1] The self when seen as a compound is when it can be interpreted as being a whole human being, body and mind, with the body being an extension of the mind.[1] It is distinct from the Cartesian Other, anything other than the Cartesian self, yet the human being version, union of body and mind, of the self is capable of interaction with the Cartesian other through extension. According to the philosopher René Descartes, there is a divide intrinsic to consciousness such that one Individual's self is the only thing they can know to certainly exist since you are not capable of knowing if other minds are able to think.[2] Cartesian Self is a term coined in retrospect to Descartes actual endeavors into Mind-Body dualism and is never actually used by him in his own writings.

Background[]

René Descartes, the namesake for the concept in itself, was a seventeenth-century philosopher heavily engaged in epistemology and metaphysics who was interested with the nature of the self, which eventually lead to him pondering the concept a great deal. The beginnings of the idea for the cartesian self come directly from René Descartes writings, more specifically the idea originated from his book Meditations on First Philosophy.[3] Descartes provided his explanation of the self primarily by going through a series of conceptions and constantly testing the validity of these same conceptions with a great deal of Philosophical skepticism. Descartes comes to the Dream argument within the Meditations to push forward the idea that our general senses were not to be trusted and could easily mislead us.[4] The skepticism employed by Descartes in the Meditations leads to the rejection of nearly everything he had come to believe up until that point aside from one point which becomes the keystone for the idea of the cartesian self.

Descartes after his rejection of all knowledge famously concluded the statement Cogito ergo sum, "I think, therefore I am", then through the use of his wax argument he is able to show how the physical is separate from innate qualities in relation to all things including the mind and body.[5] The Cartesian Self, he concluded, is thus almost entirely self-evident since it would be contradictory to deny the existence of your mind through the use of your mind.[1] Due to the thoughts Descartes had come to it he found humans are able to only truly know the self yet we can not actually know anything of the cartesian other. The nature of the self was specifically addressed in the Second Meditation wherein the narrator stated: "I am, then, in the strict sense only a thing that thinks; that is, I am a mind, or intelligence, or reason - words whose meaning I have been ignorant of until now."[3]

The mind and body aspects of cartesian are distinct from one another.[6] In the Sixth meditation Descartes goes on to describe how the mind and body stand to be distinct from one another primarily due to the fact that the mind is indivisible whereas the body is divisible. Although the mind and body remain distinct from one another the union of them can still be considered to be the cartesian self[7] Descartes claims in his sixth meditation further how we are not merely just a soul using a body since he has made the distinction between the mind and body while also proving that the mind and body form a union. Descartes explains that the mind interacts with the body through extension in a way similar to how gravity interacts with a stone.[8]

It is based on the whole of the Cartesian Pure Inquirer, where cognitive capabilities and methods of achieving knowledge are alike to all knowers. However, the "knower" (particularly to Descartes) is treated as a featureless abstract, and not an actual person.

Interpretations[]

According to Galen Strawson, the Cartesian self is pure individual consciousness and it was likened to the entity that Hume sought in the flux of perceptions, the Kantian "I think" or the pure formal unity, and Wittgenstein's conception of the subject not as part of the world but its limit.[9]

References[]

  1. ^ a b c "The mind-body Cartesian dualism and psychiatry". Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience. 20 (1): 3–3. March 2018. doi:10.31887/DCNS.2018.20.1/fthibaut. PMC 6016047. PMID 29946205.
  2. ^ Detlefsen, Karen (2013). Descartes' Meditations: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 226. ISBN 9780521111607.
  3. ^ a b Descartes, René (1986). Meditations on first philosophy : with selections from the Objections and Replies. John Cottingham. Cambridge [Cambridgeshire]: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-32966-3. OCLC 13581594.
  4. ^ Chamberlain, Colin (2020-01-14). "What Am I? Descartes's Various Ways of Considering the Self". Journal of Modern Philosophy. 2 (1): 2. doi:10.32881/jomp.30. ISSN 2644-0652.
  5. ^ Newman, Lex. "Descartes' Epistemology". plato.stanford.edu. Retrieved 2021-10-08.
  6. ^ Mehta, Neeta (2011-01-01). "Mind-body dualism: A critique from a health perspective". Mens Sana Monographs. 9 (1): 202–202.
  7. ^ "Descartes, Rene: Mind-Body Distinction | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2021-10-08.
  8. ^ Seager, William E. (1988). "Descartes on the Union of Mind and Body". History of Philosophy Quarterly. 5 (2): 119–132. ISSN 0740-0675.
  9. ^ Johnstone, Albert (1991). Rationalized Epistemology: Taking Solipsism Seriously. New York: State University of New York Press. p. 191. ISBN 079140787X.
Retrieved from ""