Free lattice

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In mathematics, in the area of order theory, a free lattice is the free object corresponding to a lattice. As free objects, they have the universal property.

Formal definition[]

Any set X may be used to generate the free semilattice FX. The free semilattice is defined to consist of all of the finite subsets of X, with the semilattice operation given by ordinary set union. The free semilattice has the universal property. The universal morphism is (FX, η), where η is the unit map η: XFX which takes xX to the singleton set {x}. The universal property is then as follows: given any map f: XL from X to some arbitrary semilattice L, there exists a unique semilattice homomorphism such that . The map may be explicitly written down; it is given by

where denotes the semilattice operation in L. This construction may be promoted from semilattices to lattices[clarification needed]; by construction the map will have the same properties as the lattice.

The construction XFX is then a functor from the category of sets to the category of lattices. The functor F is left adjoint to the forgetful functor from lattices to their underlying sets. The free lattice is a free object.

Word problem[]

The word problem for free lattices and free bounded lattices is decidable using an inductive relation. The solution has several interesting corollaries. One is that the free lattice of a three-element set of generators is infinite. In fact, one can even show that every free lattice on three generators contains a sublattice which is free for a set of four generators. By induction, this eventually yields a sublattice free on countably many generators.[1] This property is reminiscent of SQ-universality in groups.

The proof that the free lattice in three generators is infinite proceeds by inductively defining

pn+1 = x ∨ (y ∧ (z ∨ (x ∧ (y ∨ (zpn)))))

where x, y, and z are the three generators, and p0 = x. One then shows, using the inductive relations of the word problem, that pn+1 is strictly greater[2] than pn, and therefore all infinitely many words pn evaluate to different values in the free lattice FX.

The complete free lattice[]

Another corollary is that the complete free lattice (on three or more generators) "does not exist", in the sense that it is a proper class. The proof of this follows from the word problem as well. To define a complete lattice in terms of relations, it does not suffice to use the finitary relations of meet and join; one must also have infinitary relations defining the meet and join of infinite subsets. For example, the infinitary relation corresponding to "join" may be defined as

Here, f is a map from the elements of a cardinal N to FX; the operator denotes the supremum, in that it takes the image of f to its join. This is, of course, identical to "join" when N is a finite number; the point of this definition is to define join as a relation, even when N is an infinite cardinal.

The axioms of the pre-ordering of the word problem may be adjoined by the two infinitary operators corresponding to meet and join. After doing so, one then extends the definition of to an ordinally indexed given by

when is a limit ordinal. Then, as before, one may show that is strictly greater than . Thus, there are at least as many elements in the complete free lattice as there are ordinals, and thus, the complete free lattice cannot exist as a set, and must therefore be a proper class.

References[]

  1. ^ L.A. Skornjakov, Elements of Lattice Theory (1977) Adam Hilger Ltd. (see pp.77-78)
  2. ^ that is, pn~ pn+1, but not pn+1~ pn
  • Peter T. Johnstone, Stone Spaces, Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics 3, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1982. (ISBN 0-521-23893-5) (See chapter 1)
Retrieved from ""