Phenomenology (psychology)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Phenomenology within psychology (or phenomenological psychology) is the psychological study of subjective experience.[1] It's about explaining the experience from the point of view of the subject, by analyzing the words that they have spoken or had written.[2] It is an approach to psychological subject matter that has its roots in the phenomenological philosophical work of Edmund Husserl.[3]

History of Phenomenology[]

Early phenomenologists such as Husserl, Jean-Paul Sartre, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, conducted philosophical investigations of consciousness in the early 20th century. Their critiques of psychologism and positivism later influenced at least two main fields of contemporary psychology: the phenomenological psychological approach of the (the descriptive phenomenological method in psychology), including Amedeo Giorgi[3][4] and ; and the experimental approaches associated with Francisco Varela, Shaun Gallagher, Evan Thompson, and others (embodied mind thesis). Other names associated with the movement include Jonathan Smith (interpretative phenomenological analysis), , and Wolfgang Köhler. But "an even stronger influence on psychopathology came from Heidegger (1963), particularly through (1931), Blankenburg (1971), Tellenbach (1983), Binswanger (1994), and others."[5] Phenomenological psychologists have also figured prominently in the history of the humanistic psychology movement.[6]

Phenomenological Experience[]

The experiencing subject can be considered to be the person or self, for purposes of convenience. In phenomenological philosophy (and in particular in the work of Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty), "experience" is a considerably more complex concept than it is usually taken to be in everyday use. Instead, experience (or being, or existence itself) is an "in-relation-to" phenomenon, and it is defined by qualities of directedness, embodiment, and worldliness, which are evoked by the term "Being-in-the-World".[7]

The quality or nature of a given experience is often referred to by the term qualia, whose archetypical exemplar is "redness". For example, we might ask, "Is my experience of redness the same as yours?"[8] While it is difficult to answer such a question in any concrete way, the concept of intersubjectivity is often used as a mechanism for understanding how it is that humans are able to empathize with one another's experiences, and indeed to engage in meaningful communication about them. The phenomenological formulation of "Being-in-the-World", where person and world are mutually constitutive, is central here.[9]

The observer, or in some cases the interviewer, achieves this sense of understanding and feeling of relatedness to the subject's experience, through subjective analysis of the experience, and the implied thoughts and emotions that they relay in their words. [2]

Difficulties in considering subjective phenomena[]

The philosophical psychology prevalent before the end of the 19th century relied heavily on introspection. The speculations concerning the mind based on those observations were criticized by the pioneering advocates of a more scientific and objective approach to psychology, such as William James and the behaviorists Edward Thorndike, Clark Hull, John B. Watson, and B. F. Skinner. However, not everyone agrees that introspection is intrinsically problematic, such as Francisco Varela, who has trained experimental participants in the structured "introspection" of phenomenological reduction.[10]

In the early 1970s, Amedeo Giorgi applied phenomenological theory to his development of the Descriptive Phenomenological Method in Psychology. He sought to overcome certain problems he perceived from his work in psychophysics by approaching subjective phenomena from the traditional hypothetical-deductive framework of the natural sciences. Giorgi hoped to use what he had learned from his natural science background to develop a rigorous qualitative research method. His goal was to ensure that phenomenological research was both reliable and valid and he did this by seeking to make its processes increasingly measurable.[11]

Philosophers have long confronted the problem of "qualia". Few philosophers believe that it is possible to be sure that one person's experience of the "redness" of an object is the same as another person's, even if both persons had effectively identical genetic and experiential histories.[12] In principle, the same difficulty arises in feelings (the subjective experience of emotion), in the experience of effort, and especially in the "meaning" of concepts.[citation needed] As a result, many qualitative psychologists have claimed phenomenological inquiry to be essentially a matter of "meaning-making" and thus a question to be addressed by interpretive approaches.[7][13]

Psychotherapy and the phenomenology of emotion[]

Carl Rogers's person-centered psychotherapy theory is based directly on the "phenomenal field" personality theory of Combs and Snygg.[14][15] That theory in turn was grounded in phenomenological thinking.[16] Rogers attempts to put a therapist in closer contact with a person by listening to the person's report of their recent subjective experiences, especially emotions of which the person is not fully aware. For example, in relationships the problem at hand is often not based around what actually happened but, instead, based on the perceptions and feelings of each individual in the relationship. The phenomenal field focuses on "how one feels right now".

See also[]

References[]

  1. ^ Hardy Leahy, Thomas (2001). A History of Modern Psychology. New Jersey: Prentice Hall. p. 381. ISBN 0-13-017573-0.
  2. ^ Jump up to: a b Lester, Stan. (1999). An Introduction to phenomenological researchhttps://www.researchgate.net/publication/255647619_An_introduction_to_phenomenological_research
  3. ^ Jump up to: a b Giorgi, Amedeo. (1970). Psychology as a Human Science. New York : Harper & Row.
  4. ^ Giorgi, Amedeo. (2009). The Descriptive Phenomenological Method in Psychology. Duquesne University Press: Pittsburgh, PA.
  5. ^ Kraus, Albert (2010). "Existential a prioris and the phenomenology of schizophrenia" (PDF). Dialogues in Philosophy, Mental and Neuro Sciences. 3 (1): 1–7. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2017-03-03.
  6. ^ Royce, Joseph R.; Mos, Leendert P. (1981). Humanistic Psychology: Concepts and Criticisms. New York: Plenum Press. pp. xiii–xv. ISBN 978-1-4684-1073-0.
  7. ^ Jump up to: a b Langdridge, D. (2006). Phenomenological psychology: theory, research and method. Harlow: Pearson.
  8. ^ Tye, Michael, "Qualia", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/qualia/>.
  9. ^ Davidsen A. S. (2013). Phenomenological Approaches in Psychology and Health Sciences. Qualitative research in psychology, 10(3), 318–339. https://doi.org/10.1080/14780887.2011.608466
  10. ^ Varela, F.J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy to the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3330-350.
  11. ^ "Amedeo Giorgi: A Life in Phenomenology - PhenomenologyBlog". phenomenologyblog.com. Archived from the original on 23 October 2017. Retrieved 24 April 2018.
  12. ^ Tye, Michael (2018), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), "Qualia", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2021-01-20
  13. ^ Seidner, Stanley S. (1989). "Köhler's Dilemma", In Issues of Language Assessment. vol 3. Ed., Stanley S.Seidner. Springfield, Il.: State Board of Education. pp. 5–6.
  14. ^ Snygg, Donald; Combs, Arthur W. (1949). Individual Behavior: A New Frame of Reference for Psychology. New York: Harper & Brothers.
  15. ^ Rogers, Carl R. (1951) Client-Centered Therapy. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
  16. ^ Boeree, C. George (1998). "Personality Theories (Snygg and Combs' theory)". webspace.ship.edu. Archived from the original on 7 August 2007. Retrieved 7 October 2007.

External links[]

Retrieved from ""