Principia Ethica

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
The title page of Principia Ethica

Principia Ethica is a 1903 book by the British philosopher G. E. Moore, in which the author insists on the indefinability of "good" and provides an exposition of the naturalistic fallacy. Principia Ethica was influential, and Moore's arguments were long regarded as path-breaking advances in moral philosophy, though they have been seen as less impressive and durable than his contributions in other fields.[1]

Summary[]

Moore suggests that ethics is about three basic questions: (1) "what is good?", (2) "what things are good or bad in themselves?", and (3) "what is good as a means?".[2]:§2, §109

What is good[]

The first question is concerned with the nature or definition of the term "good". Moore insists that this term is simple and indefinable.[3] But two forms of goodness have to be distinguished: things that are good in themselves or intrinsically good and things that are good as causal means to other things. Our knowledge of value in itself comes from self-evident intuitions and is not inferred from other things, unlike our knowledge of goodness as a means or of duties.[2]:Preface Among the things that are good in themselves, there is an important difference between the value of a whole and the values of its parts. It is often assumed that the value of a whole just consists in the sum of the values of its parts. Moore rejects this view and insists that it fails for certain types of wholes: so-called "organic wholes".[2]:§23[4] Cases of retributive justice are examples of organic wholes. Such cases are wholes comprising two negative things, a morally vicious person and pain inflicted on this person as punishment. But the value on the whole is less negative (or maybe even positive) than the sum of the values of the two parts.[2]:§128[5] Again we have to depend on our intuitions to determine how the intrinsic value of a whole differs from the sum of the values of its parts.[2]:Preface

What things are good or bad in themselves[]

The second question of ethics asks about what kinds of things are good in themselves. Moore discusses various traditional answers to this question, especially naturalism, which he contrasts with his own approach. The main problem with naturalism in ethics is its tendency to identify value with natural properties, like pleasure in hedonism or being more evolved in "Evolutionistic Ethics".[2]:§35 He accuses such positions of committing the naturalistic fallacy in trying to define the term "good", an unanalyzable term according to Moore, in terms of natural properties.[3] If such definitions were true, then they would be uninformative tautologies, "'Pleasure is good' would be equivalent to 'Pleasure is pleasure'".[5] But, Moore argues, this is not the case, it is not a tautology but an open question whether such sentences are true.[6] This is why the definition above and naturalism with it fails.[2]:§35[5]

Moore agrees with hedonism that pleasure is good in itself, but it is not the only intrinsically valuable thing. Another important good that is valuable in itself is beauty, for example, the beauty of mountains, rivers and sunsets.[5] Moore proposes a thought experiment, the "method of isolation", as a test to determine whether something has intrinsic value.[2]:§55 The test is meant to remove any considerations of the thing being good as a means by isolating the intrinsic values.[4] The method consists in imagining a world that contains only the thing in question, for example, a world composed only of a beautiful landscape. Moore argues that such a world would be better than an ugly world, even though no one is there to enjoy it in either case, which is to show that pleasure is not the only thing good in itself.[6]

What is good as a means[]

Having answered the second question of ethics, Moore proceeds to the third question: "What is good as a means?". This question is of particular relevance since it includes the domain traditionally associated with ethics: "What ought we to do?".[2]:§88 For this it is necessary to further limit the third question since the main interest is in "actions which it is possible for most men to perform, if only they will them; and with regard to these, it does not ask merely, which among them will have some good or bad result, but which, among all the actions possible to volition at any moment, will produce the best total result".[2]:§109 So right acts are those producing the most good.[7] The difficulty with this is that the consequences of most actions are too vast for us to properly take into account, especially the long-term consequences. Because of this, Moore suggests that the definition of duty is limited to what generally produces better results than probable alternatives in a comparatively near future.[2]:§109 As the reference to causal means suggests, a detailed empirical investigation into the consequences of actions is necessary to determine what our duties are, it is not accessible to self-evident intuitive insight.[2]:§109 Whether a given rule of action turns out to be a duty depends to some extent on the conditions of the corresponding society but duties agree mostly with what common-sense recommends.[2]:§95 Virtues, like honesty, can in turn be defined as permanent dispositions to perform duties.[2]:§109

Reception[]

Principia Ethica was influential,[1] and helped to convince many people that claims about morality cannot be derived from statements of fact.[8] Clive Bell considered that through his opposition to Spencer and Mill, Moore had freed his generation from utilitarianism.[9] Principia Ethica was the bible of the Bloomsbury Group,[10] and the philosophical foundation of their aesthetic values. Leonard Woolf considered that it offered a way of continuing living in a meaningless world.[11] Moore's aesthetic idea of the organic whole provided artistic guidance for modernists like Virginia Woolf,[12] and fed into Bell's concept of Significant form.[13]

Principia Ethica also had a powerful influence on modernism through the anti-empiricism of T. E. Hulme.[14]

Socioculturally, a line can be traced from Principia Ethica to the liberal thought of Roy Jenkins,[15] as evidenced in his 1959 pamphlet Is Britain Civilised? and actuated in his subsequent Home Office reforms which established much of the institutional framework for the permissive society in England.[16]

Moore's ethical intuitionism has been seen as opening the road for noncognitive views of morality, such as emotivism.[17]

C. P. Snow sketched the enduring influence of Moore on his followers' group-belief in pleasure: "They tried to get the maximum of pleasure out of their personal relations. If this meant triangles or more complicated geometrical figures, well then, one accepted that too....If you didn't believe in pleasure, you couldn't be civilized".[18]

In A Theory of Justice (1971), John Rawls compares Moore's views to those of Hastings Rashdall in his The Theory of Good and Evil (1907).[19] Moore's views have also been compared to those of Franz Brentano, Max Scheler, and Nicolai Hartmann.[7]

Principia Ethica has been seen by Geoffrey Warnock as less impressive and durable than Moore's contributions in fields outside ethics.[1] John Maynard Keynes, an early devotee of Principia Ethica, would in his 1938 paper 'My Early Beliefs' repudiate as Utopian Moore's underlying belief in human reasonableness and decency.[20]

See also[]

References[]

  1. ^ Jump up to: a b c Warnock, Geoffrey (1995). Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 585. ISBN 0-19-866132-0.
  2. ^ Jump up to: a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Moore, George Edward (1903). Principia Ethica. Project Gutenberg.
  3. ^ Jump up to: a b Honderich, Ted (2005). "Moore, G. E". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
  4. ^ Jump up to: a b Mittelstraß, Jürgen (2005). "Moore". Enzyklopädie Philosophie und Wissenschaftstheorie. Metzler.
  5. ^ Jump up to: a b c d Hurka, Thomas (2015). "Moore's Moral Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2 January 2021.
  6. ^ Jump up to: a b Craig, Edward (1996). "Moore, George Edward". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.
  7. ^ Jump up to: a b Schneewind, J. B. (1997). Singer, Peter (ed.). A Companion to Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd. p. 153. ISBN 0-631-18785-5.
  8. ^ Schneewind, J. B. (1997). Singer, Peter (ed.). A Companion to Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd. p. 155. ISBN 0-631-18785-5.
  9. ^ Hermione Lee, Virginia Woolf (1996) p. 253
  10. ^ Lee, p. 253
  11. ^ Lee, p. 302
  12. ^ J. Briggs, Reading Virginia Woolf (2006) p. 72
  13. ^ G. Flistad, Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art (2007) p. 221
  14. ^ Levenson, p. 92
  15. ^ R. Jenkins, Nine Men of Power (1970) p. 3 and p. 12
  16. ^ J. Diski, The Sixties (2009) p. 64-5
  17. ^ R. Eldridge ed., Stanley Cavell (2003) p. 18-21
  18. ^ C. P. Snow, Last Things (1974) p. 84
  19. ^ Rawls, John (1999). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. p. 287. ISBN 0-674-00078-1.
  20. ^ Lee, p. 712

Further reading[]

  • Clive Bell, Old Friends (!956)
  • S. P. Rosenbaum ed., The Bloomsbury Group (1975)

External links[]

Retrieved from ""