The Life of the Mind

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
The Life of the Mind
Life of the Mind cover.jpg
First editions
AuthorHannah Arendt
CountryUSA
LanguageEnglish
SubjectMoral Philosophy
PublisherHarcourt Brace Jovanovich
Publication date
1977–1978
Media typePrint
Pages2 vols. 277, 278
ISBN978-0-15-651992-2

The Life of the Mind was the final work of Hannah Arendt (1906–1975), and was unfinished at the time of her death. Designed to be in three parts, only the first two had been completed and the first page of the third part was in her typewriter the evening of the day she suddenly died. The unfinished work was edited by her friend, author Mary McCarthy, and published in two volumes in 1977 and 1978.

History[]

Arendt's last major work, The Life of the Mind[1] remained incomplete at the time of her death. Arendt had long considered writing a work on the mental faculties involved in the philosophy of the mind. From the time she completed The Human Condition in 1958, she wanted to complement it by proceeding from the vita activa (active life) to the vita contemplativa (contemplative life).[a] The intent of the progression of this thought is made clear in the book.[3] She first addressed the second part in her preface to Between Past and Future (1961), which she eventually developed into The Life of the Mind, more than ten years later, her book on thinking. Her concepts became crystallized in 1963 when she wrote Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil in which she described how "thoughtlessness", the lack of thinking, could result in evil. From then onwards she became invested in the relationship between thinking and morality.[4] To develop this relationship, she realized would now require a major exploration of the Mind.[5]

An invitation to deliver the 1973–1974 Gifford Lectures in Aberdeen (the first woman to do so), provided an incentive to gather together a variety of materials including courses she had taught over the last few years on "Basic Moral Propositions," "Thinking," "The History of the Will," "Kant's Critique of Judgment", together with two essays, "Truth and Politics" and "Thinking Moral Considerations (1971)." This material she called The Life of the Mind.[5] She delivered the first set of lectures on "Thinking" in 1973, advocating what she referred to as Denken ohne Geländer (thinking without a bannister).[6] The second set of lectures on "Willing" were due to be delivered in May 1974, but during the first lecture she sustained a near fatal heart attack, and the remainder of the series were postponed till 1976. Her premature death in December 1975 prevented this, but she had completed the manuscript shortly before her death. Nevertheless, she had sufficiently recovered by late 1974 to offer the Gifford subject matter in her courses at the New School in 1974 and 1975 (where she was due to retire in 1976).[3]

The nature of the missing third part has continued to be a matter of great speculation.[4] During her visiting professorship at the New School in 1974, she presented a graduate level political philosophy class entitled, Philosophy of the Mind. It was during these class lectures that she crystallized her concepts. The class was based on her working draft of Philosophy of the Mind, which would later be edited to become Life of the Mind. Arendt's working draft was distributed to her graduate students. She conceived of a trilogy based on the mental activities of thinking, willing, and judging.

Stemming from her Gifford Lectures at the University of Aberdeen in Scotland (1972–1974),[7] her last writing focused on the first two. In a sense, Life of the Mind went beyond her previous work concerning the vita activa. In her discussion of thinking, she focuses mainly on Socrates and his notion of thinking as a solitary dialogue between oneself. This appropriation of Socrates leads her to introduce novel concepts of conscience—an enterprise that gives no positive prescriptions, but instead, tells one what I cannot do if I would remain friends with myself when I re-enter the two-in-one of thought where I must render an account of my actions to myself—and morality—an entirely negative enterprise concerned with forbidding participation in certain actions for the sake of remaining friends with oneself. She died suddenly five days after completing the second part, with the first page of Judging still in her typewriter. The task then fell to McCarthy to edit the first two parts and provide some indication of the direction of the third.[8][9]

Although Arendt's exact intentions in the third part are unknown, she did leave manuscripts (such as Thinking and Moral Considerations and Some Questions on Moral Philosophy) and lectures (Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy) concerning her thoughts on the mental faculty of Judging. The first two articles were edited and published in an anthology (Responsibility and Judgement) by Jerome Kohn, one of Arendt's assistants and a director of the Hannah Arendt Center at The New School in New York, in 2003.[10] The last was edited and published by Ronald Beiner, professor of political science at the University of Toronto, in 1982.[11] "Thinking" originally appeared in the New Yorker in a somewhat different form.

Structure[]

The book begins with the same epigraph from Cato the Elder,[b] with which she ended The Human Condition:

Numquam se plus agere quam nihil cum ageret, numquam minus solum esse quam cum solus esset
(Never is he more active than when he does nothing, never is he less alone than when he is by himself)

It was planned in two parts, "Thinking" and "Willing and Judgement". All that she had typed for "Judgement" at the time of her death were two epigraphs (see image). The first was the epigraph with which she had ended "Thinking":

Victorix causa diis placuit sed victa Catoni
(The victorious cause pleased the gods, but the vanquished pleases Cato)[c]

Arendt, here draws attention to Cato, who unlike Eichmann, clearly distinguished between right and wrong and was steadfast in his judgement. The second epigraph was this stanza by Faust from Goethe's drama of that name (II: Act V 11404–7):

Könnt' ich Magie von meinem Pfad entfernen,
Die Zaubersprüche ganz und gar verlernen,
Stünd' ich, Natur, vor dir ein Mann allein,
Da wär's der Mühe wert, ein Mensch zu sein.[13]

(If I could banish [Magic] from my track,
  Unlearn the [spells] that draw me back,
  And stand before you, Nature, as mere Man,
  [Then would it] be worth the [trouble] of being Human.)[14]

Arendt outlines her intent for "Judgement" in her postscriptum to "Thinking".[15] In the place of the unwritten "Judgement" section, McCarthy substituted relevant excerpts from Arendt's lectures on Kant's political philosophy delivered at the New School in the fall of 1970, as a guide to her thinking on the subject.[16][13]

Notes[]

  1. ^ Vita activa was Arendt's preferred title, but only her German publisher acceded to this wish[2]
  2. ^ Cato, cited by Cicero, slightly differently, in both De re publica I, 27 and De Officiis III, 1, possibly from Origines, which has not survived[12]
  3. ^ This was a phrase given to Cato the Younger by Lucan in Pharsalia, an epic depicting the Battle of Pharsalus that would doom the Roman Republic

References[]

  1. ^ Arendt 1978.
  2. ^ Kampowski 2008, p. 7.
  3. ^ a b Jonas 1977.
  4. ^ a b Kampowski 2008, p. 9.
  5. ^ a b Young-Bruehl 1982.
  6. ^ Young-Bruehl 2004, p. 453.
  7. ^ Addison 1972–1974.
  8. ^ Young-Bruehl 2004, p. 467.
  9. ^ Mckenna 1978.
  10. ^ Arendt 2009.
  11. ^ Arendt 1992.
  12. ^ Cicero 1928.
  13. ^ a b Beiner 1980.
  14. ^ von Goethe, Johann Wolfgang. Kline, A.S., translator (ed.). Faust, Parts I & II (2003 ed.). p. Part II, Act 5, Scene 5, lines 11404–7. Retrieved 5 September 2020. {{cite book}}: |editor1-first= has generic name (help)
  15. ^ Arendt 1978, p. 213.
  16. ^ Arendt 1978, p. viii.

Bibliography[]

Historical sources[]

Works by Hannah Arendt[]

External images[]

Bibliographic notes[]

  1. ^ 1st ed. Preface ix–xxv; 2nd ed. Preface to Second Edition ix–xxxvi, Preface xxxvii-l
Retrieved from ""