Delusion

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Delusion
SpecialtyPsychiatry

A delusion is a fixed belief that is not amenable to change in light of conflicting evidence.[1] As a pathology, it is distinct from a belief based on false or incomplete information, confabulation, dogma, illusion, or some other misleading effects of perception, as individuals with those beliefs are able to change or readjust their beliefs upon reviewing the evidence.

Delusions have been found to occur in the context of many pathological states (both general physical and mental) and are of particular diagnostic importance in psychotic disorders including schizophrenia, paraphrenia, manic episodes of bipolar disorder, and psychotic depression.

Types[]

Delusions are categorized into four different groups:

  • Bizarre delusion: Delusions are deemed bizarre if they are clearly implausible and not understandable to same-culture peers and do not derive from ordinary life experiences.[2] An example named by the DSM-5 is a belief that someone replaced all of one's internal organs with someone else's without leaving a scar, depending on the organ in question.
  • Non-bizarre delusion: A delusion that, though false, is at least technically possible, e.g., the affected person mistakenly believes that they are under constant police surveillance.
  • Mood-congruent delusion: Any delusion with content consistent with either a depressive or manic state, e.g., a depressed person believes that news anchors on television highly disapprove of them, or a person in a manic state might believe they are a powerful deity.
  • Mood-neutral delusion: A delusion that does not relate to the sufferer's emotional state; for example, a belief that an extra limb is growing out of the back of one's head is neutral to either depression or mania.[3]

Themes[]

In addition to these categories, delusions often manifest according to a consistent theme. Although delusions can have any theme, certain themes are more common. Some of the more common delusion themes are:

  • Delusion of control: False belief that another person, group of people, or external force controls one's general thoughts, feelings, impulses, or behaviors.[3]
  • Cotard delusion: False belief that one does not exist or that one has died.[4] Some cases also include the belief that one is immortal or that one has lost their internal organs, blood, or other body parts.[5]
  • Delusional jealousy: False belief that a spouse or lover is having an affair, with no proof to back up the claim.[3]
  • Delusion of guilt or sin (or delusion of self-accusation): Ungrounded feeling of remorse or guilt of delusional intensity.[3]
  • Delusion of mind being read: False belief that other people can know one's thoughts.[3]
  • Delusion of thought insertion: Belief that another thinks through the mind of the person.[3]
  • Delusion of reference: False belief that insignificant remarks, events, or objects in one's environment have personal meaning or significance. "Usually the meaning assigned to these events is negative, but the 'messages' can also have a grandiose quality."[3]
  • Erotomania: False belief that another person is in love with them.[3]
  • Religious delusion: Belief that the affected person is a god or chosen to act as a god.[6][7]
  • Somatic delusion: Delusion whose content pertains to bodily functioning, bodily sensations or physical appearance. Usually the false belief is that the body is somehow diseased, abnormal or changed.[3] A specific example of this delusion is delusional parasitosis: Delusion in which one feels infested with insects, bacteria, mites, spiders, lice, fleas, worms, or other organisms.
  • Delusion of poverty: Person strongly believes they are financially incapacitated. Although this type of delusion is less common now, it was particularly widespread in the days preceding state support.[8]

Grandiose delusions[]

Grandiose delusions or delusions of grandeur are principally a subtype of delusional disorder but could possibly feature as a symptom of schizophrenia and manic episodes of bipolar disorder.[9] Grandiose delusions are characterized by fantastical beliefs that one is famous, omnipotent or otherwise very powerful. The delusions are generally fantastic, often with a supernatural, science-fictional, or religious bent. In colloquial usage, one who overestimates one's own abilities, talents, stature or situation is sometimes said to have "delusions of grandeur". This is generally due to excessive pride, rather than any actual delusions. Grandiose delusions or delusions of grandeur can also be associated with megalomania.[citation needed][10]

Persecutory delusions[]

Persecutory delusions are the most common type of delusions and involve the theme of being followed, harassed, cheated, poisoned or drugged, conspired against, spied on, attacked, or otherwise obstructed in the pursuit of goals. Persecutory delusions are a condition in which the affected person wrongly believes that they are being persecuted. Specifically, they have been defined as containing two central elements:[11][page needed] The individual thinks that:

  • harm is occurring, or is going to occur
  • the persecutors have the intention to cause harm

According to the DSM-IV-TR, persecutory delusions are the most common form of delusions in schizophrenia, where the person believes they are "being tormented, followed, sabotaged, tricked, spied on, or ridiculed".[12] In the DSM-IV-TR, persecutory delusions are the main feature of the persecutory type of delusional disorder. When the focus is to remedy some injustice by legal action, they are sometimes called "querulous paranoia".[13]

Causes[]

Explaining the causes of delusions continues to be challenging and several theories have been developed.[14] One is the genetic or biological theory, which states that close relatives of people with delusional disorder are at increased risk of delusional traits. Another theory is the dysfunctional cognitive processing, which states that delusions may arise from distorted ways people have of explaining life to themselves. A third theory is called motivated or defensive delusions. This one states that some of those persons who are predisposed might suffer the onset of delusional disorder in those moments when coping with life and maintaining high self-esteem becomes a significant challenge. In this case, the person views others as the cause of their personal difficulties in order to preserve a positive self-view.[15]

This condition is more common among people who have poor hearing or sight. Also, ongoing stressors have been associated with a higher possibility of developing delusions. Examples of such stressors are immigration, low socioeconomic status, and even possibly the accumulation of smaller daily hassles.[16]

Specific delusions[]

The top two factors mainly concerned in the germination of delusions are disorder of brain functioning and background influences of temperament and personality.[17]

Higher levels of dopamine qualify as a symptom of disorders of brain function. That they are needed to sustain certain delusions was examined by a preliminary study on delusional disorder (a psychotic syndrome) instigated to clarify if schizophrenia had a dopamine psychosis.[18] There were positive results - delusions of jealousy and persecution had different levels of dopamine metabolite HVA and homovanillyl alcohol (which may have been genetic). These can be only regarded as tentative results; the study called for future research with a larger population.

It is simplistic to say that a certain measure of dopamine will bring about a specific delusion. Studies show age[19][20] and gender to be influential and it is most likely that HVA levels change during the life course of some syndromes.[21]

On the influence of personality, it has been said: "Jaspers considered there is a subtle change in personality due to the illness itself; and this creates the condition for the development of the delusional atmosphere in which the delusional intuition arises."[22]

Cultural factors have "a decisive influence in shaping delusions".[23] For example, delusions of guilt and punishment are frequent in a Western, Christian country like Austria, but not in Pakistan, where it is more likely persecution.[24] Similarly, in a series of case studies, delusions of guilt and punishment were found in Austrian patients with Parkinson's being treated with l-dopa, a dopamine agonist.[25]

Pathophysiology[]

The two-factor model of delusions posits that dysfunction in both belief formation systems and belief evaluation systems are necessary for delusions. Dysfunction in evaluations systems localized to the right lateral prefrontal cortex, regardless of delusion content, is supported by neuroimaging studies and is congruent with its role in conflict monitoring in healthy persons. Abnormal activation and reduced volume is seen in people with delusions, as well as in disorders associated with delusions such as frontotemporal dementia, psychosis and Lewy body dementia. Furthermore, lesions to this region are associated with "jumping to conclusions", damage to this region is associated with post-stroke delusions, and hypometabolism this region associated with caudate strokes presenting with delusions.[citation needed]

The aberrant salience model suggests that delusions are a result of people assigning excessive importance to irrelevant stimuli. In support of this hypothesis, regions normally associated with the salience network demonstrate reduced grey matter in people with delusions, and the neurotransmitter dopamine, which is widely implicated in salience processing, is also widely implicated in psychotic disorders.[citation needed]

Specific regions have been associated with specific types of delusions. The volume of the hippocampus and parahippocampus is related to paranoid delusions in Alzheimer's disease, and has been reported to be abnormal post mortem in one person with delusions. Capgras delusions have been associated with occipito-temporal damage and may be related to failure to elicit normal emotions or memories in response to faces.[26]

Diagnosis[]

James Tilly Matthews illustrated this picture of a machine called an “air loom”, which he believed was being used to torture him and others for political purposes.

The modern definition and Jaspers' original criteria have been criticised, as counter-examples can be shown for every defining feature.

Studies on psychiatric patients show that delusions vary in intensity and conviction over time, which suggests that certainty and incorrigibility are not necessary components of a delusional belief.[27]

Delusions do not necessarily have to be false or 'incorrect inferences about external reality'.[28] Some religious or spiritual beliefs by their nature may not be falsifiable, and hence cannot be described as false or incorrect, no matter whether the person holding these beliefs was diagnosed as delusional or not.[29] In other situations the delusion may turn out to be true belief.[30] For example, in delusional jealousy, where a person believes that their partner is being unfaithful (and may even follow them into the bathroom believing them to be seeing their lover even during the briefest of partings), it may actually be true that the partner is having sexual relations with another person. In this case, the delusion does not cease to be a delusion because the content later turns out to be verified as true or the partner actually chose to engage in the behavior of which they were being accused.

In other cases, the belief may be mistakenly assumed to be false by a doctor or psychiatrist assessing it, just because it seems to be unlikely, bizarre or held with excessive conviction. Psychiatrists rarely have the time or resources to check the validity of a person's claims leading to some true beliefs to be erroneously classified as delusional.[31] This is known as the Martha Mitchell effect, after the wife of the attorney general who alleged that illegal activity was taking place in the White House. At the time, her claims were thought to be signs of mental illness, and only after the Watergate scandal broke was she proved right (and hence sane).

Similar factors have led to criticisms of Jaspers' definition of true delusions as being ultimately 'un-understandable'. Critics (such as R. D. Laing) have argued that this leads to the diagnosis of delusions being based on the subjective understanding of a particular psychiatrist, who may not have access to all the information that might make a belief otherwise interpretable. R. D. Laing's hypothesis has been applied to some forms of projective therapy to "fix" a delusional system so that it cannot be altered by the patient. Psychiatric researchers at Yale University, Ohio State University and the Community Mental Health Center of Middle Georgia have used novels and motion picture films as the focus. Texts, plots and cinematography are discussed and the delusions approached tangentially.[32] This use of fiction to decrease the malleability of a delusion was employed in a joint project by science-fiction author Philip Jose Farmer and Yale psychiatrist A. James Giannini. They wrote the novel Red Orc's Rage, which, recursively, deals with delusional adolescents who are treated with a form of projective therapy. In this novel's fictional setting other novels written by Farmer are discussed and the characters are symbolically integrated into the delusions of fictional patients. This particular novel was then applied to real-life clinical settings.[33]

Another difficulty with the diagnosis of delusions is that almost all of these features can be found in "normal" beliefs. Many religious beliefs hold exactly the same features, yet are not universally considered delusional. For instance, if a person was holding a true belief then they will of course persist with it. This can cause the disorder to be misdiagnosed by psychiatrists. These factors have led the psychiatrist Anthony David to note that "there is no acceptable (rather than accepted) definition of a delusion."[34] In practice, psychiatrists tend to diagnose a belief as delusional if it is either patently bizarre, causing significant distress, or excessively pre-occupying the patient, especially if the person is subsequently unswayed in belief by counter-evidence or reasonable arguments.

Joseph Pierre, M.D. states that one factor that helps differentiate delusions from other kinds of beliefs is that anomalous subjective experiences are often used to justify delusional beliefs. While idiosyncratic and self-referential content often make delusions impossible to share with others,[35] Dr. Pierre suggests that it may be more helpful to emphasize the level of conviction, preoccupation, and extension of a belief rather than the content of the belief when considering whether a belief is delusional.[36]

It is important to distinguish true delusions from other symptoms such as anxiety, fear, or paranoia. To diagnose delusions a mental state examination may be used. This test includes appearance, mood, affect, behavior, rate and continuity of speech, evidence of hallucinations or abnormal beliefs, thought content, orientation to time, place and person, attention and concentration, insight and judgment, as well as short-term memory.[37]

Johnson-Laird suggests that delusions may be viewed as the natural consequence of failure to distinguish conceptual relevance. That is, irrelevant information would be framed as disconnected experiences, then it is taken to be relevant in a manner that suggests false causal connections. Furthermore, relevant information would be ignored as counterexamples.[38]

Definition[]

Although non-specific concepts of madness have been around for several thousand years, the psychiatrist and philosopher Karl Jaspers was the first to define the four main criteria for a belief to be considered delusional in his 1913 book General Psychopathology.[39] These criteria are:

  • certainty (held with absolute conviction)
  • incorrigibility (not changeable by compelling counterargument or proof to the contrary)
  • impossibility or falsity of content (implausible, bizarre, or patently untrue)[40]
  • not amenable to understanding (i.e., belief cannot be explained psychologically)[41]

Furthermore, when beliefs involve value judgments, only those which cannot be proven true are considered delusions. For example: a man claiming that he flew into the Sun and flew back home. This would be considered a delusion,[42] unless he were speaking figuratively, or if the belief had a cultural or religious source. Only the first three criteria remain cornerstornes of the current definition of a delusion in the DSM-5.

Robert Trivers writes that delusion is a discrepancy in relation to objective reality, but with a firm conviction in reality of delusional ideas, which is manifested in the "affective basis of delusion."[43]

Criticism[]

Some psychiatrists[who?] criticize the practice of defining one and the same belief as normal in one culture and pathological in another culture for cultural essentialism. They argue that it is not justified to assume that culture can be simplified to a few traceable, distinguishable and statistically quantifiable factors and that everything outside those factors must be biological since cultural influences are mixed, including not only parents and teachers but also peers, friends, and media, and the same cultural influence can have different effects depending on earlier cultural influences. Other critical psychiatrists[who?] argue that just because a person's belief is unshaken by one influence does not prove that it would remain unshaken by another. For example, a person whose beliefs are not changed by verbal correction from a psychiatrist, which is how delusion is usually diagnosed, may still change his or her mind when observing empirical evidence, only that psychiatrists rarely, if ever, present patients with such situations.[44][45]

See also[]

References[]

  1. ^ Bortolotti, Lisa (7 June 2013). "Delusions in the DSM 5". Imperfect Cognitions.
  2. ^ Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5. American Psychiatric Association. 2013.
  3. ^ Jump up to: a b c d e f g h i "Delusions". Encyclopedia of Mental Disorders. Advameg.com. Retrieved 22 April 2018.
  4. ^ Berrios G.E.; Luque R. (1995). "Cotard Syndrome: clinical analysis of 100 cases". Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica. 91 (3): 185–188. doi:10.1111/j.1600-0447.1995.tb09764.x. PMID 7625193. S2CID 8764432.
  5. ^ Ruminjo, Anne; Mekinulov, Boris (June 2008). "A Case Report of Cotard's Syndrome". Psychiatry (Edgmont). 5 (6): 28–29. ISSN 1550-5952. PMC 2695744. PMID 19727279.
  6. ^ "Religious delusions are common symptoms of schizophrenia". Retrieved 17 April 2011.
  7. ^ M, Raja. "Religious delusion" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 22 March 2012. Retrieved 17 April 2011.
  8. ^ Barker, P. 1997. Assessment in Psychiatric and Mental Health Nursing in Search of the Whole Person. UK: Nelson Thornes Ltd. P241.
  9. ^ Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders Fourth edition Text Revision (DSM-IV-TR) American Psychiatric Association (2000)
  10. ^ Kunert, Hanns Jürgen; Norra, Christine; Hoff, Paul (March 2007). "Theories of Delusional Disorders: An Update and Review". Psychopathology. 40 (3): 191–202. doi:10.1159/000100367. PMID 17337940.
  11. ^ Freeman, D. & Garety, P.A. (2004) Paranoia: The Psychology of Persecutory Delusions. Hove: PsychoIogy Press. ISBN 1-84169-522-X
  12. ^ Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-IV. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association. 2000. p. 299. ISBN 0-89042-025-4.
  13. ^ Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-IV. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association. 2000. p. 325. ISBN 0-89042-025-4.
  14. ^ Kiran C, Chaudhury S (2009). "Understanding delusions". Industrial Psychiatry Journal. 18 (1): 3–18. doi:10.4103/0972-6748.57851. PMC 3016695. PMID 21234155.
  15. ^ "Delusional Disorder". Retrieved 6 August 2010.
  16. ^ Kingston C., Schuurmans-Stekhoven J. (2016). "Life hassles and delusional ideation: Scoping the potential role of cognitive and affective mediators". Psychology and Psychotherapy: Theory, Research and Practice. 89 (4): 445–463. doi:10.1111/papt.12089. PMID 26846698.
  17. ^ Sims, Andrew (2002). Symptoms in the mind: an introduction to descriptive psychopathology. Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders. p. 127. ISBN 0-7020-2627-1.
  18. ^ Morimoto K, Miyatake R, Nakamura M, Watanabe T, Hirao T, Suwaki H (June 2002). "Delusional disorder: molecular genetic evidence for dopamine psychosis". Neuropsychopharmacology. 26 (6): 794–801. doi:10.1016/S0893-133X(01)00421-3. PMID 12007750.
  19. ^ Mazure CM, Bowers MB (1 February 1998). "Pretreatment plasma HVA predicts neuroleptic response in manic psychosis". Journal of Affective Disorders. 48 (1): 83–6. doi:10.1016/S0165-0327(97)00159-6. PMID 9495606.
  20. ^ Yamada N, Nakajima S, Noguchi T (February 1998). "Age at onset of delusional disorder is dependent on the delusional theme". Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica. 97 (2): 122–4. doi:10.1111/j.1600-0447.1998.tb09973.x. PMID 9517905. S2CID 39266698.
  21. ^ Tamplin A, Goodyer IM, Herbert J (1 February 1998). "Family functioning and parent general health in families of adolescents with major depressive disorder". Journal of Affective Disorders. 48 (1): 1–13. doi:10.1016/S0165-0327(97)00105-5. PMID 9495597.
  22. ^ Sims, Andrew (2002). Symptoms in the mind: an introduction to descriptive psychopathology. Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders. p. 128. ISBN 0-7020-2627-1.
  23. ^ Draguns JG, Tanaka-Matsumi J (July 2003). "Assessment of psychopathology across and within cultures: issues and findings". Behav Res Ther. 41 (7): 755–76. doi:10.1016/S0005-7967(02)00190-0. PMID 12781244.
  24. ^ Stompe T, Friedman A, Ortwein G, et al. (1999). "Comparison of delusions among schizophrenics in Austria and in Pakistan". Psychopathology. 32 (5): 225–34. doi:10.1159/000029094. PMID 10494061. S2CID 25376490.
  25. ^ Birkmayer W, Danielczyk W, Neumayer E, Riederer P (1972). "The balance of biogenic amines as condition for normal behaviour". J. Neural Transm. 33 (2): 163–78. doi:10.1007/BF01260902. PMID 4643007. S2CID 28152591.
  26. ^ Naasan, George. "The Anatomy of Delusions". In Lehner, T; Miller, B; State, M (eds.). Genomics, Circuits, and Pathways in Clinical Neuropsychiatry. Elsevier Science. pp. 366–369.
  27. ^ Myin-Germeys I, Nicolson NA, Delespaul PA (April 2001). "The context of delusional experiences in the daily life of patients with schizophrenia". Psychol Med. 31 (3): 489–98. doi:10.1017/s0033291701003646. PMID 11305857. S2CID 25884819.
  28. ^ Spitzer M (1990). "On defining delusions". Compr Psychiatry. 31 (5): 377–97. doi:10.1016/0010-440X(90)90023-L. PMID 2225797.
  29. ^ Young, A.W. (2000). "Wondrous strange: The neuropsychology of abnormal beliefs". In Coltheart M.; Davis M. (eds.). Pathologies of belief. Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 47–74. ISBN 0-631-22136-0.
  30. ^ Jones E (1999). "The phenomenology of abnormal belief". Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology. 6: 1–16.
  31. ^ Maher B.A. (1988). "Anomalous experience and delusional thinking: The logic of explanations". In Oltmanns T.; Maher B. (eds.). Delusional Beliefs. New York: Wiley Interscience. ISBN 0-471-83635-4.
  32. ^ Giannini AJ (2001). "Use of fiction in therapy". Psychiatric Times. 18 (7): 56.
  33. ^ AJ Giannini. Afterword. (in) PJ Farmer. Red Orc's Rage.NY, Tor Books, 1991, pp.279-282.
  34. ^ David AS (1999). "On the impossibility of defining delusions". Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology. 6 (1): 17–20.
  35. ^ Aftab, Awais (2021). "There and Back Again: Joseph Pierre, M.D." Psychiatric Times. 38 (1).
  36. ^ Pierre, JM (2001). "Faith or delusion? At the crossroads of religion and psychosis". J Psychiatr Pract. 7 (3): 163–72. doi:10.1097/00131746-200105000-00004. PMID 15990520. S2CID 22897500.
  37. ^ "Diagnostic Test List for Delusions". Retrieved 6 August 2010.
  38. ^ "A New Definition of Delusional Ideation in Terms of Model Restriction". Retrieved 6 August 2010.[permanent dead link]
  39. ^ Jaspers, Karl (1913). Allgemeine Psychopathologie. Ein Leitfaden für Studierende, Ärzte und Psychologen. Berlin: J. Springer.
  40. ^ Jaspers 1997, p. 106
  41. ^ Walker, C. (1991). "Delusion: what did Jaspers really say?". The British Journal of Psychiatry. Supplement (14): 94–103. ISSN 0960-5371. PMID 1840789.
  42. ^ "Terms in the Field of Psychiatry and Neurology". Archived from the original on 19 August 2010. Retrieved 6 August 2010.
  43. ^ Trivers, Robert (2002). Natural Selection and Social Theory: Selected Papers of Robert Trivers. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-513062-1.
  44. ^ D. Double 2006 "Critical Psychiatry: The Limits of Madness"
  45. ^ Gavin Davidson, Jim Campbell, Ciarán Shannon 2015 "Models of Mental Health"
Cited text
  • Jaspers, Karl (1997). General Psychopathology. 1. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN 0-8018-5775-9.

Further reading[]

External links[]

Classification
Retrieved from ""