Hypostasis (philosophy and religion)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Hypostasis (Greek: ὑπόστασις, hypóstasis) is the underlying state or underlying substance and is the fundamental reality that supports all else. In Neoplatonism the hypostasis of the soul, the intellect (nous) and "the one" was addressed by Plotinus.[1] In Christian theology, the Holy Trinity consists of three hypostases: Hypostasis of the Father, Hypostasis of the Son, and Hypostasis of the Holy Spirit.[2]

Ancient Greek philosophy[]

Pseudo-Aristotle used hypostasis in the sense of material substance.[3]

Neoplatonists argue that beneath the surface phenomena that present themselves to our senses are three higher spiritual principles, or hypostases, each one more sublime than the preceding. For Plotinus, these are the Soul, the Intellect, and the One.[1][4]

Christian theology[]

Italo-Greek icon, representing the Holy Trinity, Venice (16th century)

The term hypostasis has a particular significance in Christian theology, particularly in Christian Triadology (study of the Holy Trinity), and also in Christology (study of Christ).[5][6]

Hypostasis in Christian Triadology[]

In Christian Triadology (study of the Holy Trinity) three specific theological concepts have emerged throughout history,[7] in reference to number and mutual relations of divine hypostases:

  • monohypostatic (or miahypostatic) concept advocates that God has only one hypostasis;[8][9]
  • dyohypostatic concept advocates that God has two hypostases (Father and Son);[10]
  • trihypostatic concept advocates that God has three hypostases (Father, Son and the Holy Spirit).[11]

Hypostasis in Christology[]

Within Christology, two specific theological concepts have emerged throughout history, in reference to the Hypostasis of Christ:

  • monohypostatic concept (in Christology) advocates that Christ has only one hypostasis;[12]
  • dyohypostatic concept (in Christology) advocates that Christ has two hypostases (divine and human).[13]

History of use[]

In early Christian writings, hypostasis was used to denote "being" or "substantive reality" and was not always distinguished in meaning from terms like ousia ('essence'), substantia ('substance') or qnoma (specific term in Syriac Christianity).[14] It was used in this way by Tatian and Origen,[7] and also in the anathemas appended to the Nicene Creed of 325.

It was mainly under the influence of the Cappadocian Fathers that the terminology was clarified and standardized so that the formula "three hypostases in one ousia" came to be accepted as an epitome of the orthodox doctrine of the Trinity.[15] Specifically, Basil of Caesarea argues that the two terms are not synonymous and that they, therefore, are not to be used indiscriminately in referring to the godhead.[16] He writes:

The distinction between ousia and hypostases is the same as that between the general and the particular; as, for instance, between the animal and the particular man. Wherefore, in the case of the Godhead, we confess one essence or substance so as not to give variant definition of existence, but we confess a particular hypostasis, in order that our conception of Father, Son, and Holy Spirit may be without confusion and clear.[15]

This consensus, however, was not achieved without some confusion at first in the minds of Western theologians since in the West the vocabulary was different.[17] Many Latin-speaking theologians understood hypo-stasis as "sub-stantia" (substance); thus when speaking of three "hypostases" in the godhead, they might suspect three "substances" or tritheism. However, from the middle of the fifth century onwards, marked by Council of Chalcedon, the word came to be contrasted with ousia and used to mean "individual reality," especially in the trinitarian and Christological contexts. The Christian concept of the Trinity is often described as being one God existing in three distinct hypostases/personae/persons.[18]

See also[]

References[]

  1. ^ Jump up to: a b Anton 1977, p. 258-271.
  2. ^ The Encyclopedia of Christianity. 5. Fahlbusch, Erwin, Lochman, Jan Milič, Mbiti, John S., Pelikan, Jaroslav, 1923-2006, Vischer, Lukas, Bromiley, G. W. (Geoffrey William). Grand Rapids, Michigan: Eerdman. 2008. pp. 543. ISBN 978-0802824134. OCLC 39914033.CS1 maint: others (link)
  3. ^ Pseudo-Aristotle, De mundo, 4.19.
  4. ^ Neoplatonism (Ancient Philosophies) by Pauliina Remes (2008), University of California Press ISBN 0520258347, pp. 48–52.
  5. ^ Meyendorff 1989, p. 190-192, 198, 257, 362.
  6. ^ Daley 2009, p. 342–345.
  7. ^ Jump up to: a b Ramelli 2012, p. 302-350.
  8. ^ Lienhard 1993, p. 97-99.
  9. ^ Bulgakov 2009, p. 82, 143-144.
  10. ^ Lienhard 1993, p. 94-97.
  11. ^ Bulgakov 2009, p. 15, 143, 147.
  12. ^ McGuckin 2011, p. 57.
  13. ^ Kuhn 2019.
  14. ^ Meyendorff 1989, p. 173.
  15. ^ Jump up to: a b González, Justo L. (1987). A History of Christian Thought: From the Beginnings to the Council of Chalcedon. Nashville, TN: Abingdon Press. p. 307. ISBN 0-687-17182-2.
  16. ^ Turcescu 1997, p. 374-395.
  17. ^ Weedman 2007, p. 95-97.
  18. ^ González, Justo L (2005), "Hypostasis", Essential Theological Terms, Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, pp. 80–81, ISBN 978-0-664-22810-1

Sources[]

Retrieved from ""